![]() |
[Home] [Databases] [World Law] [Multidatabase Search] [Help] [Feedback] | |
England and Wales Court of Protection Decisions |
||
You are here: BAILII >> Databases >> England and Wales Court of Protection Decisions >> JB (Capacity: Consent To Sexual Relations And Contact With Others) [2019] EWCOP 39 (17 September 2019) URL: http://www.bailii.org/ew/cases/EWCOP/2019/39.html Cite as: [2020] WLR 1, [2020] 2 All ER 992, [2019] WLR(D) 517, [2020] 1 WLR 1, (2020) 23 CCL Rep 149, [2019] EWCOP 39, [2020] COPLR 1, [2019] Med LR 562, (2020) 172 BMLR 142 |
[New search] [Printable PDF version] [Buy ICLR report: [2020] 1 WLR 1] [View ICLR summary: [2019] WLR(D) 517] [Help]
IN THE MATTER OF THE MENTAL CAPACITY ACT 2005
Strand, London, WC2A 2LL |
||
B e f o r e :
____________________
A LOCAL AUTHORITY |
Applicant |
|
- and |
||
JB ((By his litigation friend, the Official Solicitor) (Capacity: Consent to Sexual Relations and Contact with Others) |
Respondent |
____________________
Mr Parishil Patel QC and Mr Ian Brownhill (instructed by the Official Solicitor) for the Respondent
Hearing date: 15 July 2019
____________________
Crown Copyright ©
Mrs Justice Roberts :
"The critical point is that, unless an understanding that the other person must be able to and must in fact consent is required for capacity in relation to sex, the criminal law would not be sufficient to protect P; and that, if the criminal law is left to regulate such conduct, it will mean that sexual offences will be committed by incapacitated people (assuming they have criminal responsibility) before the law will intervene to prevent such damaging conduct by the imposition of criminal restrictions. To permit such a situation to continue would be a derogation of responsibility by the Court of Protection. Also, criminal law would only impose a time-limited level of restriction in any event. It will be appreciated that, for people like JB, understanding that the other party must be able to and must in fact consent is a highly relevant factor to protect him from committing a criminal offence for which he could be imprisoned or, more likely, hospitalised under the MHA in circumstances where, due to his mental impairment, he cannot comprehend or acknowledge the concept of consent."
(i) any assessment of a person's capacity to consent to sexual relations must be considered through the lens of sexual contact being a fundamental human right;
(ii) "conceptual silos" in which certain categories of person are to be placed are to be avoided;
(iii) the concepts of capacity to consent to sexual relations in the civil law and criminal law are distinct.
(i) that the other person may refuse to consent to sexual contact;
(ii) that the other person may withdraw his or her consent to sexual contact at any stage of sexual activity;
(iii) that the other person cannot consent to sex if he or she is underage; and
(iv) that the other person may not be able to consent to sex because of an assessment that he or she lacks capacity to give such consent.
The legal framework and the issue of consent: the perceived lacuna
(i) The central tenet of the Mental Capacity Act 2005 requires the focus of assessment of capacity to be centred upon an evaluation of the particular individual and a specific decision. That assessment must be based upon an individual's ability to make a specific decision at the time it needs to be made, and not their ability to make decisions in general (paragraph 18).
(ii) It is important to recognise and acknowledge that, in this interpersonal context, relationships are driven as much by instinct and emotion as by rational choice. This "fundamental aspect of our humanity" is common to all regardless of whether an individual suffers from some impairment of the mind (paragraph 28). In this important judicial signpost, Hayden J was recognising and acknowledging the important point which had been made by Sir Brian Leveson P in IM v LM and Others (sub nom Re M (An Adult)) [2014] EWCA Civ 37, [2015] Fam 61, [2014] 3 All ER 491, [2014] 3 WLR 409 some four years earlier when he confirmed the court's view that the process of decision-making in relation to sexual relations even in the case of persons of full capacity is "largely visceral rather than cerebral, owing more to instinct and emotion than to analysis": see paragraph 80.
(iii) To impose a test in relation to capacity to consent to sexual relations which assumes in the decision maker a rationality which, in this context, may well be "entirely artificial" is to ignore the fact that instinct and emotion are very often intrinsic to the act itself (paragraph 29).
(iv) As confirmed by the Court of Appeal in IM v LM and Others (per Sir Brian Leveson), "the extent to which, on the facts of any individual case, there is a need either for a sophisticated, or for a more straightforward evaluation of any of the[se] four elements [i.e. the s 3(1) MCA 2005 functions of understanding information relevant to the decision; retaining that information; using or weighing that information as part of the process of making the decision; and/or communication his decision] will in the natural course of events vary from case to case and topic to topic (paragraph 32).
(v) It is important to bear in mind that depriving an individual of a sexual life in circumstances where he or she may be able to consent to it with a particular partner is to deprive that individual of a fundamental human right in circumstances where there is true consent and mutual desire (paragraph 41). A finding that an individual lacks capacity to consent to sexual relations strips the court of any power to sanction a sexual relationship between that individual in all circumstances save where capacity is regained: section 27 MCA 2005 (paragraph 34).
(vi) The issue of capacity in relation to a wide range of personal decisions is always one for judicial, and not expert, evaluation, albeit that such evaluation takes place against a broad canvas of evidence (including expert evidence) (paragraph 42).
(vii) Courts at first instance and at appellate level have repeatedly emphasised that tests in relation to capacity must be applied with the focus directed on the individual characteristics and circumstances of a protected party: (most recently) B v A Local Authority (per Sir Terence Etherton MR) (paragraph 43).
(viii) Whilst there is a public interest in the capacity test in any particular domain being formulated in relatively simple terms for ease of application, there is a countervailing public interest in ensuring that a test is both fair and "most likely to facilitate the rights of the incapacitous". " .[T]he tests require the incorporation of P's circumstances and characteristics. Whilst the test can rightly be characterised as 'issue specific" in the sense that the key criteria will inevitably be objective, there will, on occasions, be a subjective or person specific context to its application", such approach being wholly consistent with the approach endorsed by Sir Terence Etherton MR in B v A Local Authority (paragraph 48).
(ix) The applicable criteria in evaluating capacity to consent must be anchored firmly to the clear framework of ss 1 to 3 of the MCA 2005. The individual tests are not binding and are to be regarded as guidance 'to be expanded or contracted' to the facts of the particular case. They must be construed purposively so as to promote a protected party's autonomy and his or her vulnerability (paragraph 51).
(x) In terms of risk evaluation, the purpose of the MCA 2005 is not to provide some absolute protection whereby an individual is excluded entirely from future harm. Any such evaluation can only be undertaken on the basis of known facts. "It is not the objective of the MCA to pamper or to nursemaid the incapacitous, rather it is to provide the fullest experience of life and with all its vicissitudes. This must be kept in focus when identifying the appropriate criteria for assessing capacity; it is not to be regarded as applicable only to a consideration of best interests" (paragraph 56).
(xi) In terms of the interrelationship between criminal and civil law, there is a danger in assuming that the concepts of consent underpinning the criminal law are transferable to issues of capacity under the MCA 2005. Criminal courts and the Court of Protection are engaged in different issues involving separate consideration of social policy and personal autonomy. "In the context of criminal law the test to be applied is a retrospective assessment of whether consent was truly given. In the Court of Protection, the assessment is prospective, contemplating assessment of capacity to consent with both specific individuals and generally" (paragraphs 61 and 62).
"81. It is for that reason also that the ability to use and weigh information is unlikely to loom large in the evaluation of capacity to consent to sexual relations. It is not an irrelevant consideration: indeed (as we have emphasised) the statute mandates that it be taken into account, but the notional process of using and weighing information attributed to the protected person should not involve a refined analysis of the sort which does not typically inform the decision to consent to sexual relations made by a person of full capacity. That is the point which Munby J was seeing to make in X City Council v MB [2006] 2 FLR 968, para 84 It is precisely this point which Hedley J was driving in A NHS Trust v P [2013] EWHC 50 (Fam) at [10] when he observed that
"the intention of the Act is not to dress an incapacitous person in forensic cotton wool but to allow them as far as possible to make the same mistakes that all other human beings are at liberty to make and not infrequently do."
82. We agree. Perhaps yet another way of expressing the same point is to suggest that the information typically, and we stress typically, regarded by persons of full capacity as relevant to the decision whether to consent to sexual relations is relatively limited. The temptation to expand that field of information in an attempt to simulate more widely informed decision-making is likely to lead to what Bodey J rightly identified as both paternalism and a derogation from personal autonomy."
The statutory principles
"The principles
(1) The following principles apply for the purposes of this Act.
(2) A person must be assumed to have capacity unless it is established that he lacks capacity.
(3) A person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision unless all practicable steps to help him to do so have been taken without success.
(4) A person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision merely because he makes an unwise decision.
(5) An act done, or decision made, under this Act for or on behalf of a person who lacks capacity must be done, or made, in his best interests.
(6) Before the act is done, or the decision is made, regard must be had to whether the purpose for which it is needed can be as effectively achieved in a way that is less restrictive of the person's rights and freedom of action."
"People who lack capacity
(1) For the purposes of this Act, a person lacks capacity in relation to a matter if at the material time he is unable to make a decision for himself in relation to the matter because of an impairment of, or a disturbance in the functioning of, the mind or brain.
(2) It does not matter whether the impairment or disturbance is permanent or temporary.
(3) A lack of capacity cannot be established merely by reference to (a) a person's age or appearance, or (b) a condition of his, or an aspect of his behaviour, which might lead others to make unjustified assumptions about his capacity.
(4) In proceedings under this Act or any other enactment, any question whether a person lacks capacity within the meaning of this Act must be decided on the balance of probabilities."
"Inability to make decisions
(1) For the purposes of section 2, a person is unable to make a decision for himself if he is unable (a) to understand the information relevant to the decision, (b) to retain that information, (c) to use or weigh that information as part of the process of making the decision, or (d) to communicate his decision (whether by talking, using sign language or any other means).
(2) A person is not to be regarded as unable to understand the information relevant to a decision if he is able to understand an explanation of it given to him in a way that is appropriate to his circumstances (using simple language, visual aids or any other means).
(3) The fact that a person is able to retain the information relevant to a decision for a short period only does not prevent him from being able to make the decision.
(4) The information relevant to a decision includes information about the reasonably foreseeable consequences of (a) deciding one way or another, or (b) failing to make the decision."
The evolution/development of the test in relation to consent to sexual relations
"39. So the question that I have to answer is this: in order to be able to consent to sex does a person need to have a proper and full(ish) awareness and understanding that sex should only be done by people over 16, and that it should be consensual ? It is not an answer to the question to observe that sex with minors, and non-consensual sex, are horrible peversions. There are plenty of paedophiles out there who through warped ideology actually believe that it is morally acceptable to have sex with children. Equally, the prisons have numerous rapists within their walls. But paedophiles and rapists have the capacity to consent to sex.
40. [Counsel for the local authority] says that this argument is over-intellectual. We are dealing here, he says, with mentally incapacitated people, who in terms of section 2(1) of the Mental Capacity Act 2005 are suffering impairment of, or a disturbance in the functioning of, the mind or brain. We are not talking about peverts who obviously have the capacity to consent to sex. This is true enough, but I believe that to import these knowledge requirements into the capacity test elevates it to a level considerably above the very simple and low level test propounded by Munby J namely "sufficient rudimentary knowledge of what the act comprises and of its sexual character": X City Council v MB [2006] 2 FLR 968 , para 74.
41. In his evidence Dr Hall emphasised that the need for consent is one of the very first messages that is conveyed to people with learning disabilities who are being taught about sex. Nothing I say is intended to diminish that obviously vital message. There is a difference, however, between the teaching of what is right and wrong in the pursuit of sex, and what level of understanding and intelligence is needed to be capable of consenting to it." (my emphasis)
"42. I therefore conclude that the capacity to consent to sex remains act-specific and requires an understanding and awareness of: the mechanics of the act; that there are health risks involved, particularly the acquisition of sexually transmitted and sexually transmissible infection; that sex between a man and a woman may result in the woman becoming pregnant."
" . The act of intercourse is often understood as having an element of self-giving qualitatively different from any other human contact. Nevertheless, the challenge remains: can it be articulated into a workable test ? Again I have thought long and hard about this and acknowledge the difficulty inherent in the task. In my judgment one can do no more than this: does the person whose capacity is in question understand that they do have a choice and that they can refuse ? That seems to me to be an important aspect of capacity and is as far as it is really possible to go over and above an understanding of the physical component." (paragraph 25)
(i) the mechanics of the act;
(ii) that there are health risks involved (including pregnancy); and
(iii) that he or she has a choice and can refuse."
"21. It is of course important to remember that possession of capacity is quite distinct from the exercise of it by the giving or withholding of consent. Experience in the family courts tends to suggest that in the exercise of capacity humanity is all too often capable of misguided decision-making and even downright folly. That of itself tells one nothing of capacity itself which requires a quite separate consideration.
22. These issues, moreover, resonate both in criminal and in civil law. It is of course highly desirable that there should be no unnecessary inconsistency between them. However, capacity arises in different contexts. In the criminal law it arises most commonly in respect of a single incident and a particular person where the need to distinguish between capacity and consent may have no significance on the facts. In a case such as the present, however, capacity has to be decided in isolation from any specific circumstances of sexual activity as the purpose of the capacity inquiry is to justify the prevention of any such circumstances arising. There is of course no absolute distinction between capacity in civil and capacity in criminal law, it is merely that they fall to be considered in very different contexts and often, perhaps, for different purposes."
Later, at paragraph 26, Hedley J reached this conclusion:
" The focus of the criminal law must inevitably be both act and person and situation sensitive; the essential protective jurisdiction of this court, however, has to be effective to work on a wider canvas."
"48. In our judgment, the distinction drawn by Mostyn J and Hedley J is extremely important and sight of it must not be lost. The criminal law bites only retrospectively. Has this conduct, in these circumstances and with the knowledge or understanding of these participants, contravened the law ? In the context of section 30 of the 2003 Act, provided the inability to refuse is because of or for a reason related to mental disorder, it does not matter whether it is because he or she lacks sufficient understanding of the nature or reasonably foreseeable consequences of what is being done, or for any other reason. The civil law requires prospective assessment in the light of the particular circumstances of the affected individual. The criminal law does not only protect those whom the courts have declared lack capacity."
"i) the sexual nature and character of the act of sexual intercourse, the mechanics of the act;
ii) the reasonably foreseeable consequences of sexual intercourse, namely pregnancy;
iii) the opportunity to say no; i.e. to choose whether or not to engage in it and the capacity to decide whether to give or withhold consent to sexual intercourse;
iv) that there are health risks involved, particularly the acquisition of sexually transmitted and transmissible infections;
v) that the risks of sexually transmitted infection can be reduced by the taking of precautions such as the use of a condom" (paragraph 43).
" . The argument before Hayden J in London Borough of Tower Hamlets v NB was presumably that the conclusion in IM does not preclude the tailoring of relevant information to accommodate the individual characteristics of the person being assessed. We heard no arguments on these points and do not need to decide them on the present appeals since it was not contended by the OS that anything in Cobb J's guideline was inapplicable because of B's personal characteristics. The criticism of the OS is that parts (iii), (iv) and (v) in their present form are inapposite in all cases." (see paragraph 49)
"51. We understood Mr Karim to submit that part (iii) of Cobb J's list confuses the relevant information for determining the capacity to consent to sexual relations with the actual decision whether or not to give consent. This does not seem to us to be a point of any substance on the correctness of Cobb J's decision that B lacked capacity to consent to sexual relations. Mr Karim referred us to the observation of Parker J in The London Borough of Southwark v KA [2016] EWCOP 20 at [52] that "consent is not part of the 'information' test as to the nature of the act or its foreseeable consequences. It goes to the root of capacity itself". Her point, which is plainly correct, was that awareness of the ability to consent to or refuse sexual relations is more than just an item of relevant information. As she elaborated at [53]:
"The ability to understand the concept of and the necessity of one's own consent is fundamental to having capacity: in other words that "P knows that she/he has a choice and can refuse"."[my emphasis]
"At the risk of labouring the point further, I am emphasising that the tests require the incorporation of P's circumstances and characteristics. Whilst the test can be rightly characterised as 'issue specific', in the sense that the key criteria will inevitably be objective, there will, on occasions, be a subjective or person specific context to its application."
"54. That there is no need to evaluate an understanding of pregnancy when assessing consent to sexual relations in same sex relationships or with women who are infertile or post-menopausal strikes me as redundant of any contrary argument. Nor, with respect to what has been advanced in this case, can it ever be right to assess capacity on a wholly artificial premise which can have no bearing at all on P's individual decision taking. It is inconsistent with the philosophy of the MCA 2005. Further, it is entirely irreconcilable with the Act's defining principle in Sec. 1(2) 'a person must be assumed to have capacity unless it is established that he lacks capacity'."
Discussion and analysis
Should the need to understand the voluntary nature of sexual activities extend to an understanding of full consent from sexual partners ?
"Based on descriptions of his previous and ongoing behaviours, this is most likely to take the form of sexual harassment through the form of repeated, unwanted sexually explicit messages to females whose numbers he has obtained or whom he contacts through social media or dating sites. [JB] has also been observed to have limited social boundaries around women, particularly those who are vulnerable but also women in pubs or clubs whom he has approached whilst dancing. Additionally he acknowledges not being able to judge women's reactions to him and that he is unwilling to directly ask for clarification of these issues. In these and similar situations the risk is of [JB] sexually touching these women without consent. In terms of vulnerable women who do not have the capacity to consent to sexual relations, there is a risk of [JB] not recognising or respecting this fact, resulting in the potential for rape to occur."
" [T]he risks posed by a young adult who is very interested in sex but has no understanding of the need for the other person to consent is plainly a live issue in tis case, unlike the academic risks in the NB case. Further, as a matter of policy, that type of risk can never be irrelevant, for there will always be a potential victim of a criminal offence who deserves protection, not just by the criminal law when the risk has eventuated, but P should also be protected from the adverse consequences of such acts by mental capacity law."
"It is not a question of P understanding the criminal law; more that P must understand that the other person must consent as a matter of fact, from their words and conduct .. Far from discriminating against P if the "relevant information" is held to include an appreciation that the other must consent, it would discriminate against P if he was permitted to have sex with people absent any understanding that the other must consent, for it would deprive him of the protection which the law should give him against the obvious adverse and serious consequences of behaving in such a way."
"My Lords, it is difficult to think of an activity which is more person- and situation-specific than sexual relations. One does not consent to sex in general. One consents to this act of sex with this person at this time and in this place. Autonomy entails the freedom and the capacity to make a choice of whether or not to do so. This is entirely consistent with the respect for autonomy in matters of private life which is guaranteed by article 8 of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms. The object of the Sexual Offences Act 2003 was to get away from the previous 'status'-based approach which assumed that all 'defectives' lacked capacity, and thus denied them the possibility of making autonomous choices, while failing to protect those whose mental disorder deprived them of autonomy in other ways."
"[42] These types of impediment which affect mental functioning to the extent of undermining the ability to make a capacitous decision must be carefully distinguished from a person's specific features which do not undermine capacity in the same way. Another person's view of the suitability of a particular sexual partner for the person whose capacity is being considered is irrelevant to the determination of whether or not that person has capacity. To take account of such a feature in determining capacity would be risking the importation of 'best interests', and runs directly counter to section 1(4) of the 2005 Act ('a person is not to be treated as unable to make a decision merely because he makes an unwise decision'). Furthermore, as Baroness Hale pointed out in R v Cooper (Gary Anthony), to apply such a consideration to the determination of capacity would be a gross failure to respect a person's autonomy, protected by article 8 of the European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Freedoms in relation to one of the most intimate and personal aspects of their private life."
"56. Since it is all too possible for sexual contact to take place, and does take place, without consent the necessity for the consent of a partner does not obviously form part of the capacity test, particularly since the issue of consent in the criminal law can give rise to complex debate as to mens rea, particularly in cases of apparent consent or lack of explicit communication of consent."
As I have already made clear in paragraph 44 of my judgment, this passage was specifically endorsed by the full Court of Appeal in the very recent decision in B v A Local Authority (and see below).
(i) a person is presumed to have capacity unless it is established that he or she lacks capacity (section 1(2));
(ii) he or she is not to be treated as unable to make a decision unless all practicable steps to help him or her to do so have been taken without success (section 1(3));
(iii) he or she is not to be treated as lacking capacity merely because his or her decision is unwise (section 1(4));
(iv) a lack of capacity in relation to a particular subject matter or domain arises in circumstances where, at the material time, a person is unable to make a decision for himself or herself because of an impairment of, or a disturbance in the functioning of, the mind or brain (section 2(1));
(iv) capacity determinations are specific to particular matters which arise for decision at the time a determination is required and are resolved on the balance of probabilities (section 2(4)). Thus if a local authority or other public body or third party alleges that a person lacks capacity to make a particular decision, it is for that body, entity or person to prove that fact on the basis of the ordinary civil standard;
(v) the ability of a person to make a decision depends upon his or her ability to understand, retain or use or weigh the information relevant to that decision and to communicate that decision (section 3(1)). That information has to be presented to the person in a way that is appropriate to his or her circumstances (section 3(2)) but a person may be capacitous in relation to a particular decision even if he/she can only retain that information for a short period of time (section 3(3));
(vi) the definition or content of 'relevant information' for these purposes will depend on the nature of the decision to be made but will include the reasonably foreseeable consequences of making that decision or failing to make that decision (section 3(4));
(vii) if a person is found to lack capacity, a decision taken on his or her behalf by the court or someone else must be in the person's best interests taking account of all his or her relevant circumstances including certain mandatory requirements listed in section 4 of the MCA 2005.
"Whilst P may often be assessed as neither possessing, nor being likely to ever gain, capacity to consent to sexual relations when a general test is applied, P's characteristics / situation, will include include the intended sexual partner, who may well be more labile in temperament or circumstances and likely to require frequent re-assessment (in terms of the risks presented) if adequate safeguarding is to exist.
Hence, were certain criteria to be excluded from the relevant information, P and their partner would need careful monitoring to ensure risks have not arisen that require reassessment including the previously excluded criteria.
The domain of sexual relations is also more likely to require consideration of a number of third parties/partners over P's lifetime, either consecutively or concurrently and would significantly increase the number of assessments required, which by their very nature can constitute an intrusive examination of a sensitive area of any individual's life."
What is the correct approach to dealing with issues of contact with others and the support which JB may need when he is in the company of someone to whom he feels sexually attracted ?
(i) whether TZ had the capacity to make a decision whether or not an individual with whom he wished to have sexual relations was safe, and, if not,
(ii) whether he had the capacity to make a decision as to the support he was likely to require when having contact with such an individual.
Note 1 Dr Thrift, Chartered Consultant Clinical Psychologist; addendum report dated 26 September 2018 [2/F:225] [Back] Note 2 i.e. an understanding of (i) the mechanics of the act; (ii) the health risks involved; and (iii) the risk of pregnancy in heterosexual sex [Back] Note 3 LBX v K & L [2013] EWHC 3230 (Fam), para [43] per Theis J as approved by the CA in B v A Local Authority [2019] EWCA Civ 913 at [20] and approved at [62] [Back] Note 4 LBX v K & L (above) at [48] approved by the CA in B v A Local Authority at [22] [Back] Note 5 Re A (Capacity: Social Media and Internet Use: Best Interests) [2019] EWCOP 2 [Back]